One of the most striking aspects of the build up to the TUC
demonstration in March, and the continuing Occupation of St. Pauls, has been the
opposition both inside
and outside
of the movement to link our local struggles to the Arab Spring. The reasoning
goes: we have ‘democracy’ here; we have ‘freedoms’; we have ‘human rights’; we
are not ‘repressed’ by the state; we are not fighting ‘despots’. Some have even
argued that, by drawing inspiration from Tahrir Square, we are insulting our Egyptian counterparts. Others have suggested that it is all merely an excuse to riot.
The overall tendency of these arguments is to suggest that
since that Egyptians live under a system based on political coercion, their
struggles are valid and honourable. Because we live within a system based on
political consent, our struggles are naïve and indulgent. But this double
patronisation of both Arab and Western protestors reveals a latent ruling-class
bias which overshadows and skews the definitions of what should and shouldn’t
be considered legitimate protest.
Consent
The whole basis for distinguishing between Arab and Western
struggles overlooks the interrelation of both coercion and consent as
reproductive mechanisms of ruling-class power. One of the greatest of
achievements of Antonio Gramsci’s work is to show how rather than a guarantee
of freedom, consent acts as the primary mechanism for the maintenance of
ruling-class hegemony under capitalism. In the Prison Notebooks Gramsci argues that by ‘manufacturing consent’
through political, ideological and cultural practices – bargaining, concession
making, propaganda etc. – dominant class interests are maintained and
reproduced without the need for state coercion.
This is not to say that such processes do not constitute a
substantial part of any form of ruling-class reproduction. But consent takes on
an especial character under capitalism due to the distinctiveness of
its material reproduction. One of the defining elements of capitalism
is the supposed freedom of labour. While under slavery and feudalism, labourers
were coerced into working for the
ruling-class, under capitalism workers formally consent to do so. This in turn obscures the specifically
non-political, economic, form of coercion (the unfreedom of having to work in order to buy food,
clothes, shelter etc) and exploitation (surplus labour, labour made to work for
more than it is paid).
In turn, the ideological legitimation of consent also takes
on characteristics specific to capitalism. Because capitalism has, in theory,
dispensed itself of political and cultural loci of power, consent is
established on the basis of our political
freedom – our right to vote, our right to freedom of expression, our right
to free assembly, etc. Mechanisms of economic
coercion – the commodification of labour-power and the exploitative relation
between capital and labour are considered off limits. Equally the material and ideological
bases of consent frame the parameters of what is considered legitimate protest
– while political repression is considered fair game, economic repression is
not. Struggles for democracy: good. Strikes: bad. Taken together, these
ideological and material moments serve to both legitimise and disguise
ruling-class domination; our political freedom both justifies and veils our
economic unfreedom.
The attempted division of the Arab Spring from resistance
movements in the West should be seen within this very context of consent
generation. Creating a distinction between the two represents an integral part
of the ideological reproduction of ruling class power. For it is precisely
through such consent generating discourse that the division between the Arab
Spring and Western struggles is articulated: the Arab Spring is about their
tyrannical system of rule, that is, political coercion. Their challenge to the
system or to the ruling-class is therefore legitimate. The struggle in say,
Britain, is different. It is simply about public sector cuts, issues of
supposed economic necessity. It is therefore not about our system of rule, not
about our ruling-class. Why? Because ‘we have democracy, we have freedom of
speech, we have a right to protest.’
Coercion
However, for Gramsci, consent constituted only the formal appearance
of coercion. Put differently, consent can be better defined as ‘consented coercion’. The true nature of this relation
becomes clear in moments of ruling-class crisis, where the ideological
mechanisms that underpin consent break down, and the ‘mask of consent’ is
removed thus revealing the naked force of coercion. In other words, where
consent fails, coercion picks up the pieces and re-asserts ruling-class
hegemony through the use of state violence, repression and suppression.
Three hypotheses can be drawn from this observation. Firstly,
it gives us a more appropriate basis from which we can distinguish between the
Arab Spring and its Western counterparts. In the Arab region ruling-class
consent was (for a variety of historical and conjunctural reasons) weaker, and
therefore tended to break down quicker and more suddenly than in the West. Consequently,
coercion played a much more dominant role in the maintenance of ruling-class
hegemony than in the West.
Secondly, consent and coercion are merely two sides of the
same coin. The dominance of one form over another should not blind us to the
fact that both are expressions of the same ruling-class hegemony. As Richard
Seymour points out, the ruling-classes in the West are becoming attuned to and
aware of cracks in ruling-class ideology. So, as consent fails as a mechanism for
ruling-class reproduction, coercion will increasingly step in and take its
place.
Thirdly, the break down of consent is therefore not confined
to Arab nations. Indeed, there is a growing body of evidence that we are
witnessing a crisis of consent in the heartlands of global capitalism. From the
undemocratic power of finance, to legal restrictions on the occupation of public space, from technocratic coups, to the draconian sentencing of protesters, more people are becoming aware that our supposed political
freedoms are often used to mask the coercive hegemony of the ruling-class.
Crisis
To summarise, Gramsci’s analysis of consent and coercion is
instructive in that it highlights the interconnection between the two. But it
also demonstrates that the two exist in perpetual tension and are prone to
crisis. If the whole structure of ruling-class consent is built on supposed
political freedoms, what happens when
the ruling classes have to resort to the brutal methods of state repression? What happens when the UK
government seeks to ban protests during the Olympic games? What happens when the US state does this:
Indeed, what happens when the ruling military junta in Egypt uses Western practices of political coercion as a justification for their own brutal repression of demonstrators in Tahrir Square?
The more the ruling-class depends on coercion to reproduce
its power, the more it will undermine and weaken the basis of its own consent.
The more it will become like Mubarak’s Egypt, or Ben Ali’s Tunisia, or Assad’s
Syria. The more it will become self-evident that there is no fundamental
difference between Arab and Western struggles.
As with the Arab Spring, the political coercion of movements
such as Occupy Wall Street has the potential to popularise and broaden the
movement to sections of society that would have otherwise been opposed or
indifferent – liberals, trade union leaders, mainstream media, political
parties, religious groups, etc. The embryo of such broad based solidarity has
already been witnessed in the Occupy movements either side of the Atlantic. So
as we look to build for November 30th
and beyond, establishing and maintaining the unity of various resistance
movements should form the bedrock of any political strategy of resistance.
No comments:
Post a Comment